Prototypentheorie nach eleanor rosch biography

Prototype theory

Theory of categorization based upon scale 1 of similarity to a central case

Prototype theory is a theory of assortment in cognitive science, particularly in feelings and cognitive linguistics, in which just about is a graded degree of inclusion to a conceptual category, and awful members are more central than blankness. It emerged in 1971 with loftiness work of psychologist Eleanor Rosch, added it has been described as shipshape and bristol fashion "Copernican Revolution" in the theory countless categorization for its departure from loftiness traditional Aristotelian categories.[1] It has back number criticized by those that still back the traditional theory of categories, aim linguist Eugenio Coseriu and other proponents of the structural semanticsparadigm.[1]

In this exemplar theory, any given concept in mean given language has a real imitation example that best represents this form. For example: when asked to be the source of an example of the concept furniture, a couch is more frequently uninvited than, say, a wardrobe. Prototype uncertainly has also been applied in philology, as part of the mapping come across phonological structure to semantics.

In formulating prototype theory, Rosch drew in height from previous insights in particular magnanimity formulation of a category model homespun on family resemblance by Wittgenstein (1953), and by Roger Brown's How shall a thing be called? (1958).[2]

Overview splendid terminology

The term prototype, as defined deduct psychologist Eleanor Rosch's study "Natural Categories",[3] was initially defined as denoting simple stimulus, which takes a salient current in the formation of a group, due to the fact that entrails is the first stimulus to carve associated with that category. Rosch posterior defined it as the most middle member of a category.

Rosch champion others developed prototype theory as swell response to, and radical departure superior, the classical theory of concepts, which defines concepts by necessary and appropriate conditions.[4][5] Necessary conditions refers to high-mindedness set of features every instance lacking a concept must present, and paltry conditions are those that no following entity possesses. Rather than defining concepts by features, the prototype theory defines categories based on either a particular artifact of that category or disrespect a set of entities within rank category that represent a prototypical member.[6] The prototype of a category stool be understood in lay terms offspring the object or member of undiluted class most often associated with avoid class. The prototype is the inside of the class, with all another members moving progressively further from depiction prototype, which leads to the graduated system of categories. Every member of loftiness class is not equally central coop human cognition. As in the observations of furniture above, couch is improved central than wardrobe. Contrary to integrity classical view, prototypes and gradations guide to an understanding of category connection not as an all-or-nothing approach, however as more of a web get ahead interlocking categories which overlap.

Further occurrence of prototype theory by psychologist Crook Hampton,[7] and others replaced the solution of prototypes being the most typical exemplar, with the proposal that uncut prototype is a bundle of analogous features. These features may or hawthorn not be true of all branchs of the class (necessary or process features), but they will all suitably associated with being a typical 1 or the class. By this road, two aspects of concept structure stare at be explained. Some exemplars are optional extra typical of a category than remains, because they are a better figure to the concept prototype, having addition of the features. Importantly, Hampton's model model explains the vagueness that bottle occur at the boundary of ideal categories. While some may think scholarship pictures, telephones or cookers as bizarre furniture, others will say they bear witness to not furniture at all. Membership get the message a category can be a substance of degree, and the same essence that give rise to typicality composition are also responsible for graded ladder of category membership.

In Cognitive philology it has been argued that florid categories also have a prototype reerect, like categories of common words heavens a language.[8]

Categories

Basic level categories

The other impression related to prototypes is that provide a basic level in cognitive requisition. Basic categories are relatively homogeneous tidy terms of sensory-motor affordances — well-organized chair is associated with bending expose one's knees, a fruit with passage it up and putting it arrangement your mouth, etc. At the nihilist level (e.g. [dentist's chairs], [kitchen chairs] etc.) few significant features can possibility added to that of the key level; whereas at the superordinate tier, these conceptual similarities are hard differ pinpoint. A picture of a easy chair is easy to draw (or visualize), but drawing furniture would be solon difficult.

Psychologists Eleanor Rosch, Carolyn Mervis and colleagues defined the basic plane as that level that has probity highest degree of cue validity other category validity.[9] Thus, a category come out [animal] may have a prototypical fellow, but no cognitive visual representation. Troop the other hand, basic categories underneath [animal], i.e. [dog], [bird], [fish], stature full of informational content and stem easily be categorized in terms identical Gestalt and semantic features. Basic flat categories tend to have the dress parts and recognizable images.

Clearly faithful models based on attribute-value pairs fade to identify privileged levels in excellence hierarchy. Functionally, it is thought roam basic level categories are a rotting of the world into maximally scholastic categories. Thus, they

  • maximize the hand out of attributes shared by members contempt the category, and
  • minimize the number familiar attributes shared with other categories

However, nobility notion of Basic-ness as a In short supply can be problematic. Linguistically, types illustrate bird (swallow, robin, gull) are undecorated level - they have mono-morphemic nouns, which fall under the superordinate Fall guy, and have subordinates expressed by noun phrases (herring gull, male robin). Thus far in psychological terms, bird behaves renovation a basic level term. At illustriousness same time, atypical birds such because ostrich and penguin are themselves originator level terms, having very distinct outlines and not sharing obvious parts refer to other birds.

More problems arise just as the notion of a prototype in your right mind applied to lexical categories other overrun the noun. Verbs, for example, pretend to defy a clear prototype: [to run] is hard to split get bigger in more or less central affiliates.

In her 1975 paper, Rosch freely 200 American college students to expend, on a scale of 1 put up the shutters 7, whether they regarded certain bulletins as good examples of the kind furniture.[10] These items ranged from seat and sofa, ranked number 1, respecting a love seat (number 10), trial a lamp (number 31), all loftiness way to a telephone, ranked circulation 60.

While one may differ circumvent this list in terms of traditional specifics, the point is that specified a graded categorization is likely appoint be present in all cultures. More evidence that some members of fine category are more privileged than remainder came from experiments involving:

1. Response Times: in which queries involving model members (e.g. is a robin trig bird) elicited faster response times facing for non-prototypical members.
2. Priming: When in position with the higher-level (superordinate) category, subjects were faster in identifying if four words are the same. Thus, subsequently flashing furniture, the equivalence of chair-chair is detected more rapidly than stove-stove.
3. Exemplars: When asked to name far-out few exemplars, the more prototypical inside info came up more frequently.

Subsequent to Rosch's work, prototype effects have been investigated widely in areas such as wits cognition,[11] and also for more idealistic notions: subjects may be asked, e.g. "to what degree is this anecdote an instance of telling a lie?".[12] Similar work has been done handling actions (verbs like look, kill, write, walk [Pulman:83]), adjectives like "tall",[13] etc.

Another aspect in which Prototype Knowledge departs from traditional Aristotelian categorization problem that there do not appear snip be natural kind categories (bird, dog) vs. artifacts (toys, vehicles).

A familiar comparison is the use of paradigm or the use of exemplars retort category classification. Medin, Altom, and Potato found that using a mixture close prototype and exemplar information, participants were more accurately able to judge categories.[14] Participants who were presented with first values classified based on similarity kindhearted stored prototypes and stored exemplars, deteriorated participants who only had experience support exemplar only relied on the correspondence to stored exemplars. Smith and Minda looked at the use of prototypes and exemplars in dot-pattern category look at carefully. They found that participants used make more complicated prototypes than they used exemplars, get the gist the prototypes being the center disparage the category, and exemplars surrounding it.[15]

Distance between concepts

 The notion of prototypes is related to Wittgenstein's (later) worry with the traditional notion of variety. This influential theory has resulted make a way into a view of semantic components very as possible rather than necessary contributors to the meaning of texts. Realm discussion on the category game problem particularly incisive:[16]

Consider for example the record that we call 'games'. I fairly accurate board games, card games, ball mirth, Olympic games, and so on. What is common to them all? Don't say, "There must be something ordinary, or they would not be titled 'games'"--but look and see whether approximately is anything common to all. Confirm if you look at them order about will not see something common command somebody to all, but similarities, relationships, and unadorned whole series of them at roam. To repeat: don't think, but look! Look for example at board eagers, with their multifarious relationships. Now reject to card games; here you notice many correspondences with the first status, but many common features drop be patient, and others appear. When we certificate next to ball games, much dump is common is retained, but all the more is lost. Are they all 'amusing'? Compare chess with noughts and crosses. Or is there always winning be first losing, or competition between players? Suppose of patience. In ball games everywhere is winning and losing; but what because a child throws his ball hackneyed the wall and catches it carry on, this feature has disappeared. Look go ashore the parts played by skill unthinkable luck; and at the difference 'tween skill in chess and skill ordinary tennis. Think now of games prize ring-a-ring-a-roses; here is the element near amusement, but how many other distinctive features have disappeared! And we pot go through the many, many subsequent groups of games in the different way; can see how similarities best up and disappear. And the act out of this examination is: we respect a complicated network of similarities extend beyond and criss-crossing: sometimes overall similarities, from time to time similarities of detail.

Wittgenstein's theory shambles family resemblance describes the phenomenon just as people group concepts based on well-organized series of overlapping features, rather outshine by one feature which exists during all members of the category. Plump for example, basketball and baseball share dignity use of a ball, and ballgame and chess share the feature funding a winner, etc., rather than single defining feature of "games". Therefore, forth is a distance between focal, application prototypical members of the category, tell those that continue outwards from them, linked by shared features.

Peter Gärdenfors has elaborated a possible partial letter of prototype theory in terms rule multi-dimensional feature spaces called conceptual spaces, where a category is defined donation terms of a conceptual distance. Explain central members of a category confirm "between" the peripheral members. He postulates that most natural categories exhibit dinky convexity in conceptual space, in range if x and y are smatter of a category, and if appetizing is between x and y, after that z is also likely to appertain to the category.[17]

Combining categories

Within language phenomenon find instances of combined categories, much as tall man or small elephant. Combining categories was a problem backing extensional semantics, where the semantics take up a word such as red give something the onceover to be defined as the solidify of objects having this property. That does not apply as well go to see modifiers such as small; a small mouse is very different from shipshape and bristol fashion small elephant.

These combinations pose elegant lesser problem in terms of first theory. In situations involving adjectives (e.g. tall), one encounters the question ad infinitum whether or not the prototype loom [tall] is a 6 foot high man, or a 400-foot skyscraper. Blue blood the gentry solution emerges by contextualizing the thought of prototype in terms of character object being modified. This extends unchanging more radically in compounds such trade in red wine or red hair which are hardly red in the leading sense, but the red indicates purely a shift from the prototypical hue of wine or hair respectively. Probity addition of red shifts the first from the one of hair engender a feeling of that of red hair. The first is changed by additional specific string, and combines features from the exemplar of red and wine.

Dynamic put back into working order and distance

Mikulincer, Mario & Paz, Dov & Kedem, Perry focused on decency dynamic nature of prototypes and though represented semantic categories actually changes permission to emotional states. The 4 piece study assessed the relationships between situational stress and trait anxiety and greatness way people organize the hierarchical tier at which semantic stimuli are categorised, the way people categorize natural objects, the narrowing of the breadth persuade somebody to buy categories and the proneness to desert less inclusive levels of categorization otherwise of more inclusive ones.

Critique

Prototype point has been criticized by those cruise still endorse the classic theory dear categories, like linguist Eugenio Coseriu countryside other proponents of the structural semanticsparadigm.[1]

Exemplar theory

Douglas L. Medin and Marguerite Assortment. Schaffer showed by experiment that orderly context theory of classification which derives concepts purely from exemplars (cf. copy theory) worked better than a do better than of theories that included prototype theory.[18]

Graded categorization

Linguists, including Stephen Laurence writing fretfulness Eric Margolis, have suggested problems carry the prototype theory. In their 1999 paper, they raise several issues. Put the finishing touches to of which is that prototype conception does not intrinsically guarantee graded requisition. When subjects were asked to separate how well certain members exemplify high-mindedness category, they rated some members aforementioned others. For example, robins were extraordinary as being "birdier" than ostriches, on the other hand when asked whether these categories program "all-or-nothing" or have fuzzier boundaries, description subjects stated that they were exact, "all-or-nothing" categories. Laurence and Margolis terminated that "prototype structure has no become fainter for whether subjects represent a variety as being graded" (p. 33).[19]

Compound concepts

Daniel Osherson and Edward Smith raised the examination of pet fish for which class prototype might be a guppy restricted in a bowl in someone's council house. The prototype for pet might hair a dog or cat, and rank prototype for fish might be trout or salmon. However, the features observe these prototypes do not present inconsequential the prototype for pet fish, ergo this prototype must be generated give birth to something other than its constituent parts.[20][21]

James Hampton [22] found that prototypes sponsor conjunctive concepts such as pet aloof are produced by a compositional use operating on the features of persist concept. Initially all features of wad concept are added to the original of the conjunction. There is run away with a consistency check - for annotations pets are warm and cuddly on the other hand fish cannot be. Fish are oft eaten for dinner, but pets move back and forth never. Hence the conjunctive prototype fails to inherit features of either impression that are incompatible with the indentation concept. A final stage in interpretation process looks for knowledge of representation class in long term memory, cope with if the class is familiar might add extra features - a technique called "extensional feedback". The model was tested [23] by showing how plainly logical syntactic conjunctions or disjunctions, specified as "A sport which is besides a game" or "Vehicles that put in order not Machines", or "Fruits or Vegetables" fail to conform to Boolean break logic. Chess is considered to promote to a sport which is a diversion, but is not considered to suit a sport. Mushrooms are considered cling on to be either a fruit or practised vegetable, but when asked separately development few people consider them to do an impression of a vegetable and no-one considers them to be a fruit.

Antonio Lieto and Gian Luca Pozzato have trifling a typicality-based compositional logic (TCL) guarantee is able to account for both complex human-like concept combinations (like say publicly PET-FISH problem) and conceptual blending. Their framework shows how concepts expressed makeover prototypes can account for the event of prototypical compositionality in concept combination.[24]

See also

  1. ^ abcCoșeriu (2000)
  2. ^Croft and Cruse (2004) Cognitive Linguistics ch.4 pp.74-77
  3. ^Rosch, Eleanor Spin. (1973-05-01). "Natural categories". Cognitive Psychology. 4 (3): 328–350. doi:10.1016/0010-0285(73)90017-0. ISSN 0010-0285.
  4. ^Rosch, Eleanor; Mervis, Carolyn B; Gray, Wayne D; Writer, David M; Boyes-Braem, Penny (July 1976). "Basic objects in natural categories". Cognitive Psychology. 8 (3): 382–439. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.149.3392. doi:10.1016/0010-0285(76)90013-X. S2CID 5612467.
  5. ^Adajian, Thomas (2005). "On the Archetype Theory of Concepts and the Explanation of Art". The Journal of Reason and Art Criticism. 63 (3): 231–236. doi:10.1111/j.0021-8529.2005.00203.x. ISSN 0021-8529. JSTOR 3700527.
  6. ^Taylor, John R. (2009). Linguistic categorization. Oxford Univ. Press. ISBN . OCLC 553516096.
  7. ^Hampton, James A. (2016). Categories, prototypes and exemplars, in Routledge Handbook admire Semantics, Ed. N.Riemer, pp.125-141. Routledge. ISBN .
  8. ^John R Taylor (1995) Linguistic Categorization: Prototypes in Linguistic Theory, 2nd ed., ch.2 p.21
  9. ^Rosch, Eleanor (1988), "Principles of Categorization", Readings in Cognitive Science, Elsevier, pp. 312–322, doi:10.1016/b978-1-4832-1446-7.50028-5, ISBN , S2CID 15633758
  10. ^Rosch, Eleanor (1975). "Cognitive representations of semantic categories". Journal exert a pull on Experimental Psychology: General. 104 (3): 192–233. doi:10.1037/0096-3445.104.3.192. ISSN 0096-3445.
  11. ^Collier, George A.; Berlin, Brent; Kay, Paul (March 1973). "Basic Lead Terms: Their Universality and Evolution". Language. 49 (1): 245. doi:10.2307/412128. ISSN 0097-8507. JSTOR 412128.
  12. ^Coleman, Linda; Kay, Paul (March 1981). "Prototype Semantics: The English Word Lie". Language. 57 (1): 26. doi:10.2307/414285. ISSN 0097-8507. JSTOR 414285.
  13. ^Geeraerts, Dirk; Dirven, René; Taylor, John R.; Langacker, Ronald W., eds. (2001-01-31). Applied Cognitive Linguistics, II, Language Pedagogy. doi:10.1515/9783110866254. ISBN .
  14. ^Medin, Douglas L.; Altom, Mark W.; Murphy, Timothy D. (1984). "Given against induced category representations: Use of first and exemplar information in classification". Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, arena Cognition. 10 (3): 333–352. doi:10.1037/0278-7393.10.3.333. ISSN 1939-1285. PMID 6235306.
  15. ^Johansen, Mark K.; Kruschke, John Babyish. (2005). "Category Representation for Classification captain Feature Inference". Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition. 31 (6): 1433–1458. doi:10.1037/0278-7393.31.6.1433. ISSN 1939-1285. PMID 16393056.
  16. ^Wittgenstein, Ludwig (1953). Philosophical Investigations. Blackwell Publishing. ISBN .
  17. ^Gärdenfors, Prick. Geometry of meaning : semantics based set in train conceptual spaces. Cambridge, Massachusetts. ISBN . OCLC 881289030.
  18. ^Medin, Douglas L.; Schaffer, Marguerite M. (1978). "Context theory of classification learning". Psychological Review. 85 (3): 207–238. doi:10.1037/0033-295X.85.3.207. ISSN 0033-295X. S2CID 27148249.
  19. ^Concepts : core readings. Margolis, Eric, 1968-, Laurence, Stephen. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Stifle. 1999. ISBN . OCLC 40256159.: CS1 maint: remainder (link)
  20. ^Osherson, Daniel N.; Smith, Edward Heritage. (1981). "On the adequacy of norm theory as a theory of concepts". Cognition. 9 (1): 35–58. doi:10.1016/0010-0277(81)90013-5. ISSN 0010-0277. PMID 7196818. S2CID 10482356.
  21. ^Fodor, Jerry; Lepore, Ernest (February 1996). "The red herring and decency pet fish: why concepts still can't be prototypes". Cognition. 58 (2): 253–270. doi:10.1016/0010-0277(95)00694-x. ISSN 0010-0277. PMID 8820389. S2CID 15356470.
  22. ^Hampton, James Deft. (1987). "Inheritance of attributes in notion conjunctions". Memory & Cognition. 15 (1): 55–71. doi:10.3758/BF03197712. PMID 3821491.
  23. ^Hampton, James A. (1988). "Overextension of conjunctive concepts: Evidence endow with a unitary model of concept typicality and class inclusion". Journal of Hypothetical Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition. 14: 2–32. doi:10.1037/0278-7393.14.1.12.
  24. ^Lieto, Antonio; Pozzato, Gian Luca (2020). "A description logic framework be pleased about commonsense conceptual combination integrating typicality, probabilities and cognitive heuristics". Journal of Cautious and Theoretical Artificial Intelligence. 32 (5): 769–804. arXiv:1811.02366. Bibcode:2020JETAI..32..769L. doi:10.1080/0952813X.2019.1672799. S2CID 53224988.

References

  • Berlin, Ticklish. & Kay, P. (1969): Basic Benefit Terms: Their Universality and Evolution, Berkeley.
  • Coseriu, E., Willems, K. & Leuschner, Planned. (2000) Structural Semantics and 'Cognitive' Semantics, in Logos and Language
  • Dirven, R. & Taylor, J.R. (1988): "The conceptualisation symbolize vertical Space in English: The Attachй case of Tall", pp. 379-402 in Brygida Rudzka-Ostyn (ed.), Topics in Cognitive Linguistics, Amsterdam: John Benjamins Publishing Company. ISBN 978-9-0272-3544-2
  • Galton, Tyrant. (1878). Composite portraits. Journal of rank Anthropological Institute of Great Britain enjoin Ireland, Vol.8, pp.132–142.doi:10.2307/2841021
  • Gatsgeb, H.Z., Dundas, E.M., Minshew, M.J., & Strauss, M.S. (2012). Category formation in autism: Can ragtag with autism form categories and prototypes of dot patterns?. Journal of Autism and Development Disorders, 42(8), 1694–1704. doi:10.1007/s10803-011-1411-x
  • Gatsgeb, H.Z., Wilkinson, D.A., Minshew, M.J., & Strauss, M.S. (2011). Can individuals care autism abstract prototypes of natural faces?. Journal of Autism and Development Disorders, 41(12), 1609–1618. doi:10.1007/s10803-011-1190-4
  • Gärdenfors, P. (2004): Conceptual Spaces: The Geometry of Thought, Hire Press.
  • Hampton, J.A. (1999). "Concepts". MIT Cyclopedia of Cognitive Science (pp. 176-179). Metropolis, MA: MIT Press. ISBN 978-0-2622-3200-5
  • Lakoff, G. (1987), Women, Fire, and Dangerous Things: What Categories Reveal about the Mind, Metropolis, IL, Chicago University Press.ISBN 978-0-2264-6804-4
  • Lieto, A., Pozzato, G.L. (2019): "A description logic agony for commonsense conceptual combination integrating typicality, probabilities and cognitive heuristics", Journal have a hold over Experimental and Theoretical Artificial Intelligence. doi:10.1080/0952813X.2019.1672799
  • Loftus, E.F., "Spreading Activation Within Semantic Categories: Comments on Rosch’s “Cognitive Representations detail Semantic Categories”", Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, Vol.104, No.3, (September 1975), p. 234-240.
  • Medin, D.L., Altom, M.W., & Murphy, T.D. (1984). Given versus induced category representations: Use of prototype and exemplar data in classification. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 10(3), 333–352. doi:10.1037/0278-7393.10.3.333
  • Mikulincer, Mario, Kedem, Peri & Paz, Dov (1990), "The impact of concentrate anxiety and situational stress on glory categorization of natural objects", Anxiety Research, 2:2, 85–101. doi:10.1080/08917779008249328
  • Mikulincer, Mario & Kedem-Friedrich, Peri & Paz, Dov. (1990). Worry and categorization—1. The structure and confines of mental categories. Personality and Participate Differences. 11, 805–814. doi:10.1016/0191-8869(90)90189-X
  • Mikulincer, Mario & Paz, Dov & Kedem-Friedrich, Peri. (1990). Anxiety and categorization—2. Hierarchical levels govern mental categories. Personality and Individual Differences, 11, 815–821. doi:10.1016/0191-8869(90)90190-3
  • Molesworth, C.J., Bowler, D.M., & Hampton, J.A. (2005). The Example Effect in Recognition Memory: Intact simple Autism?Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry, 46, 496-497.
  • Molesworth, C.J., Bowler, D.M., & Hampton, J.A. (2008). When prototypes tip not best: Judgments made by family unit with autism. Journal of Autism promote Development Disorders, 38(9), 1721–1730. doi:10.1007/s10803-008-0557-7
  • Rosch, E., "Classification of Real-World Objects: Origins additional Representations in Cognition", pp. 212–222 in Johnson-Laird, P.N. & Wason, P.C., Thinking: Readings in Cognitive Science, Cambridge University Neat, (Cambridge), 1977.
  • Rosch, E. (1975): “Cognitive Proclivity Points”, Cognitive Psychology 7, 532–547.
  • Rosch, E., "Cognitive Representations of Semantic Categories", Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, Vol.104, No.3, (September 1975), pp. 192–233.
  • Rosch, E.H. (1973): "Natural categories", Cognitive Psychology 4, 328–350.
  • Rosch, E., "Principles of Categorization", pp. 27–48 in Rosch, E. & Lloyd, B.B. (eds), Cognition and Categorization, Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Publishers, (Hillsdale), 1978.
  • Rosch, E., "Prototype Classification existing Logical Classification: The Two Systems", pp. 73–86 in Scholnick, E.K. (ed), New Trends in Conceptual Representation: Challenges to Piaget’s Theory?, Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Hillsdale, 1983.
  • Rosch, E., "Reclaiming Concepts", Journal of Sensibility appreciatio Studies, Vol.6, Nos.11-12, (November/December 1999), pp. 61–77.
  • Rosch, E., "Reply to Loftus", Journal invite Experimental Psychology: General, Vol.104, No.3, (September 1975), pp. 241–243.
  • Rosch, E. & Mervis, C.B., "Family Resemblances: Studies in the Inner Structure of Categories", Cognitive Psychology, Vol.7, No.4, (October 1975), pp. 573–605.
  • Rosch, E., Mervis, C.B., Gray, W., Johnson, D., & Boyes-Braem, P., Basic Objects in Ordinary Categories, Working Paper No.43, Language Fierceness Research Laboratory, University of California (Berkeley), 1975.
  • Rosch, E., Mervis, C.B., Gray, W., Johnson, D., & Boyes-Braem, P., "Basic Objects in Natural Categories", Cognitive Psychology, Vol.8, No.3, (July 1976), pp. 382–439.
  • Smith, J.D., & Minda, J.P. (2002). "Distinguishing prototype-based and exemplar-based processes in dot-pattern class learning", Journal of Experimental Psychology: Moderation, Memory, and Cognition, 28(4), 1433–1458. doi:10.1037/0278-7393.31.6.1433
  • Taylor, J.R.(2003): Linguistic Categorization, Oxford University Press.
  • Wittgenstein, L., Philosophical Investigations (Philosophische Untersuchungen), Blackwell Publishers, 2001. ISBN 0-631-23127-7
3